did-you-know? rent-now

Amazon no longer offers textbook rentals. We do!

did-you-know? rent-now

Amazon no longer offers textbook rentals. We do!

We're the #1 textbook rental company. Let us show you why.

9780674004894

Economic Sentiments

by
  • ISBN13:

    9780674004894

  • ISBN10:

    0674004892

  • Format: Hardcover
  • Copyright: 2001-05-16
  • Publisher: Harvard Univ Pr
  • Purchase Benefits
  • Free Shipping Icon Free Shipping On Orders Over $35!
    Your order must be $35 or more to qualify for free economy shipping. Bulk sales, PO's, Marketplace items, eBooks and apparel do not qualify for this offer.
  • eCampus.com Logo Get Rewarded for Ordering Your Textbooks! Enroll Now
List Price: $65.50

Summary

In a brilliant recreation of the epoch between the 1770s and the 1820s, Emma Rothschild reinterprets the ideas of the great revolutionary political economists to show us the true landscape of economic and political thought in their day, with important consequences for our own. Her work alters the readings of Adam Smith and Condorcet--and of ideas of Enlightenment--that underlie much contemporary political thought. Economic Sentiments takes up late-eighteenth-century disputes over the political economy of an enlightened, commercial society to show us how the "political" and the "economic" were intricately related to each other and to philosophical reflection. Rothschild examines theories of economic and political sentiments, and the reflection of these theories in the politics of enlightenment. A landmark in the history of economics and of political ideas, her book shows us the origins of laissez-faire economic thought and its relation to political conservatism in an unquiet world. In doing so, it casts a new light on our own times.

Table of Contents

Introduction 1(6)
Economic Dispositions
7(45)
The History of Sentiments
7(2)
Civilized and Commercial Society
9(3)
The Unfrightened Mind
12(3)
Two Kinds of Enlightenment
15(2)
The Devil Himself
17(3)
Heroic Dispositions
20(2)
A Sort of Inner Shuddering
22(3)
The Cold Light of Reason and the Warmth of Economic Life
25(4)
Seeing the State as in a Picture
29(5)
Indulgence and Indifference
34(5)
The Light of History
39(8)
The Enlightenment and the Present
47(5)
Adam Smith and Conservative Economics
52(20)
This Famous Philosopher
52(3)
Scotland in the 1790s
55(2)
Economic and Political Freedom
57(4)
The Liberal Reward of Labor
61(3)
One-Sided Rationalistic Liberalism
64(2)
Smith's Real Sentiments
66(6)
Commerce and the State
72(15)
A Reciprocal Dependence
72(1)
Scarcities, Dearths, and Famines
73(3)
Poverty and General Equilibrium
76(2)
Turgot's Policies against Famine
78(3)
Interpretations of Smith and Turgot
81(2)
The Lapse of Time
83(4)
Apprenticeship and Insecurity
87(29)
A Strange Adventure
87(1)
It Is But Equity, Besides
88(2)
Corporations and Competition
90(5)
Education and Apprenticeship
95(5)
A State of Nonage
100(5)
The Apprenticeship: A Digression on the Slave Trade
105(2)
Uncertain Jurisprudence
107(6)
History and Institutions
113(3)
The Bloody and Invisible Hand
116(41)
The Invisible Hand of Jupiter
116(2)
Tremble, Unfortunate King!
118(3)
Intentions and Interests
121(5)
Political Influence
126(3)
Clerical Systems
129(2)
Smith's ``Stoicism''
131(3)
Order and Design
134(2)
A Persuasive Device
136(2)
Explanation and Understanding
138(5)
Greatest Possible Values
143(3)
Evolved Orders
146(7)
Two Shortcomings of Liberal Thought
153(4)
Economic and Political Choice
157(38)
Raton Was Quite Astonished ...
157(3)
General Economic Interdependence
160(2)
Giving the Impression of Doing Nothing
162(3)
The Soul Discouraged
165(4)
Poverty, Taxes, and Unsalubrious Factories
169(6)
Formal Methods
175(5)
Social Choice and Economic Procedures
180(6)
Discussions and Constitutions
186(2)
Pelion and Ossa
188(7)
Condorcet and the Conflict of Values
195(23)
Cold, Descriptive Cartesian Reason
195(2)
Diversity and Uniformity
197(6)
The Indissoluble Chain
203(1)
Civilized Conflict
204(2)
Inconsistent Universalism
206(3)
Domestic Virtues
209(3)
The Imaginary Enlightenment
212(2)
The Liberty of Thought and Discussion
214(4)
A Fatherless World
218(37)
A Different Enlightenment
218(3)
Smith and Condorcet
221(2)
Uncertainty and Irresolution
223(5)
A System of Sentiments
228(4)
Civilized Political Discussion
232(4)
Economic Sentiments
236(10)
A World Unrestored
246(4)
Suitable Equality
250(5)
Notes 255(88)
Acknowledgments 343(2)
Index 345

Supplemental Materials

What is included with this book?

The New copy of this book will include any supplemental materials advertised. Please check the title of the book to determine if it should include any access cards, study guides, lab manuals, CDs, etc.

The Used, Rental and eBook copies of this book are not guaranteed to include any supplemental materials. Typically, only the book itself is included. This is true even if the title states it includes any access cards, study guides, lab manuals, CDs, etc.

Excerpts


Introduction

This book is about laissez-faire when it was new. The half century from the 1770s to the 1820s was a time of enthusiasm and fear in economic life; of excitement over the projects of merchants and manufacturers, resentment over restrictions on buying and selling, confidence in the "liberal plan of equality, liberty and justice" to which Adam Smith looked forward in 1776, anxiety about what Napoleon in St. Helena, studying the Wealth of Nations , described in 1816 as the new system of "freedom of commerce for all," which had "agitated all imaginations" in the "furious oscillations" of modern times.

    Economic life was intertwined, in these turbulent times, with the life of politics and the life of the mind. Economic thought was intertwined with political, philosophical, and religious reflection. The life of cold and rational calculation was intertwined with the life of sentiment and imagination. The sources of economic opulence were to be found, it was thought, in political and legal institutions, and in the history of the human mind. They were to be found, most of all, in the dispositions or ways of thinking of individuals; in the disposition to discuss and dispute and to think about the future; in the unfrightened mind.

    To look at the economic thought of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries in the setting of the political, legal, and philosophical disputes of the times is to cast light, I hope, on the events and the dispositions of those times. It is to see the past more clearly; to glimpse a now unfamiliar landscape of economic and political life.

    But the book is also about the present. For the disputes with which I will be concerned are in an odd and disconcerting sense the disputes of our own present times. They are disputes which have continued in one form or another--over laissez-faire and the state, over respect and disrespect for established institutions, over reason and faith--throughout the entire period which separates Adam Smith's times and our own. They are even newly modern, in the new circumstances of the beginning of the twenty-first century. The rhetoric of freedom of commerce is as conspicuous now as it was in the period which preceded and followed the French Revolution. So is the sense of living in a society of universal commerce and universal uncertainty. It is this new world, too, with which the book is concerned.

    The treatises and pamphlets of the late eighteenth century about the reform of commerce were considered, very soon, to be disquisitions of only limited and technical interest. The Wealth of Nations , Jean-Baptiste Say wrote in 1803, was a "vast chaos of just ideas, pell-mell with pieces of positive knowledge," overfull of historical digressions and "particular facts." Caroline, the ingenuous interlocutor in Jane Marcet's Conversations on Political Economy of 1817, complained that economic science "is about custom-houses, and trade, and taxes, and bounties, and smuggling, and paper-money, and the bullion-committee, &c," and that Adam Smith's work is no more than "a jargon of unintelligible terms."

    My objective, in what follows, is to look back, beyond the preoccupations of the early nineteenth century, at an earlier and more open political economy. I will be concerned mostly with two eighteenth-century writers--Condorcet and Smith--who have become emblems of the cold, hard, and rational enlightenment. They are opposite emblems in several respects. Condorcet has come to epitomize the cold, universalistic enlightenment of the French Revolution; the "utopian" enlightenment. Smith has come to epitomize the one-sided, reductionist enlightenment of laissez-faire economics; the "conservative" enlightenment. But both philosophers were preoccupied, as will be seen, with similar details of the regulation of commerce. Both were concerned with what Condorcet described, in 1790, as "the restoration of the most complete freedom" in commercial policy. Both were also interested in economic dispositions, and in the politics of a universe of uncertainty. Both were interested in economic life as a process of discussion, and as a process of emancipation. To rediscover a different political economy, I will suggest, is also to rediscover a different, and more open, enlightenment.

    Political economy, in the period with which the book is concerned, was seen already as a science of sorts. Condorcet indeed complained, as early as 1771, about the deluded use of "the language of geometry" in "the economic sciences," and one of Turgot's theological opponents wrote of "economic science," with its "useless, lewd, and twisted" views, that it was already, in 1780, "beginning to go a little out of fashion." But the intertwining of economic, religious, political, and moral thought--the sense that there is only a shifting, indistinct frontier between economic and political relationships, or between economic life and the rest of life--is far more characteristic of the beginning of the period than of the end.

    It was "since Adam Smith," in Jean-Baptiste Say's description, that political economy, defined "as the science concerned with wealth," had been distinguished from the quite different discipline of politics. The economist George Pryme, the first professor of political economy at the University of Cambridge, looked back with some alarm, in 1823, at Smith's jumbling together of economic and political concerns. "Since his time the distinction between Political Economy and pure Politics, has been generally observed," Pryme wrote. Political economy had become an inoffensive and orderly subject; "though it may seem less interesting than Political Philosophy, its utility is more extensive, since it is applicable alike to a despotism and to a democracy."

    The new circumscription of political economy corresponded to the classificatory disposition of the times. It was suited to what Hegel described in 1807 as the "method of labelling all that is in heaven and earth" in the museum of science as in a "synoptic table like a skeleton with scraps of paper stuck all over it, or like the rows of closed and labelled boxes in a grocer's stall." Condorcet himself contributed to the subsequent professional organization of political economy through his theory of social science, and through his projects of the 1790s (including those for the establishment of special chairs in the application of mathematics to the political and moral sciences, and in political economy). Smith commented with characteristic coolness, a generation earlier, on the new taxonomic spirit; in an early draft of the Wealth of Nations , from the 1760s, he says of the subdivisions of modern philosophy--"mechanical, chemical, astronomical, physical, metaphysical, moral, political, commercial and critical"--that their effect is such that "more work is done upon the whole and the quantity of science is considerably increased by it."

    But the new circumscription and circumspection of political economy also corresponded to the exigent circumstances of post-Revolutionary politics. The context of political economy at the very end of the eighteenth century was the prospect, described by Malthus in 1798 in the first paragraph of his Essay on the Principle of Population , that the French Revolution would "scorch up and destroy the shrinking inhabitants of the earth." The French economists were inculpated, as will be seen, in the anti-Jacobin and anti-philosophical writings of the 1790s. Like the supporters of political reform in Kant's Contest of Faculties , also of 1798, economic reformers were subject to the charge of "innovationism, Jacobinism and conspiracy, constituting a menace to the state." The disposition of enlightenment, or the uncertain and insubordinate way of thinking of commercial society, was inculpated in the moral revolutions of the times.

    The economic writings with which I will be concerned belong to a different, more innocent world. Smith and Condorcet, Hume and Turgot wrote, sometimes at great length, about freedom of commerce; none of them was a political economist in the professional sense that became familiar in the early years of the nineteenth century. All of them also wrote about philosophy, the history of science, the history of ideas, and about politics. All were, on occasion, public officials. Hume died in 1776, Turgot in 1781, Smith in 1790, and Condorcet in 1794, a few weeks before the end of the Jacobin Terror; they belonged to an earlier universe of thought. When Thomas Jefferson drew up "a course of reading" in 1799, he included Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding , Smith's Wealth of Nations , and Condorcet's Esquisse d'un tableau historique des progrès de l'esprit humain . Condorcet's own objective, in the Esquisse des progrès , was to describe the history of ideas about the mind and morality and the law, from the earliest sages to "the profound analyses of the Lockes, the Smiths, the Turgots." For Arthur Condorcet O'Connor, the Irish general who married Condorcet's daughter Eliza, "the Turgots, the Condorcets, the Smiths" were the "fathers of the science" of political economy, whose principles, including "the eternal principle of equality," had been overturned by the "new sect of so-called economists" of the post-Revolutionary reconstruction.

    It is this earlier world which I will try to describe. Chapter 1 is about late eighteenth-century descriptions of sentiments and dispositions in economic life, and the idea of an unfrightened mind; of a way of thinking of individuals, emancipated, at least from time to time, from fears of violence, injustice, and vexation. Chapter 2 is about Adam Smith's reputation following his death in 1790, including his reputation for an unseemly relationship to the principles of the French Revolution, and some of the ways in which the renown of political economy changed, in France, England and Scotland, over the decade of the 1790s. Chapters 3 and 4 are about two of the great controversies in economic policy which shaped subsequent views of eighteenth-century economic thought. The first, discussed in Chapter 3, is the dispute over free commerce in subsistence food, over the relations between commerce and government in the grain trade, and over the transition to commercial freedom. The second, discussed in Chapter 4, is the dispute over apprenticeship and mastership guilds: over laissez-faire in the market for labor, public instruction, and the relations between commerce and government in industry.

    The idea of the "invisible hand," which was presumed, for much of the twentieth century, to constitute a unifying theme of Smith's economic thought, is the subject of Chapter 5. Smith's own view of the invisible hand, I will suggest, was different and more skeptical. It should be understood in the setting of other, and at the time more familiar invisible hands: the "bloody and invisible hand" of Macbeth's providence, or the "invisible hand" which rebuffs and then hovers over the unfortunate hero of Voltaire's Oedipe . The idea of the invisible hand raises troublesome questions both about the relationship between economic and religious thought and about the relationship between the political and economic choices of individuals; about the pursuit of self-interest within rules, and the transformation of wealth into political power, including the power to transform rules.

    Chapter 6 is concerned with Condorcet's efforts, in his writings on economic policy, to explore closely related questions about the rules and the dispositions of competition, about buying and selling political influence, and about the depiction of discursive economic subjects. Chapter 7 is about some of Condorcet's criticisms of the cold, universal, and all-imbuing philosophy which has been seen as characteristic of the eighteenth-century enlightenment, and about an idea--the "indissoluble chain" of truth, virtue and happiness--which was taken, again for much of the twentieth century, as a unifying theme of Condorcet's political thought. In Chapter 8 I will look at theories of economic and political sentiments, and at the reflection of these theories in the politics of enlightenment, including the politics of an uncertain or fatherless world.

    The detailed disputes in which Smith and Condorcet were engaged, over duties on salt or apprenticeship regulations or restrictions on the export of rams, are largely unfamiliar to readers today. The political relationships of the period--the identification of the reforming left and the conservative right, of the state and the market, of the disposition and the sect of enlightenment--are also unfamiliar. We still live, at the outset of the twenty-first century, in a world which is defined, in important respects, by the events of the French Revolution and of the post-Revolutionary restoration; by the coalition of laissez-faire economic policy and political conservatism which was established in opposition to the revolutionary violence of the 1790s, and which came to dominate nineteenth-century political institutions.

    But we also live, in the new circumstances of the early twenty-first century, in a post-restoration world. Political institutions are more free of the fear of revolution now than at any time in the nineteenth or twentieth centuries. The rhetoric of the endlessness of commerce is more unquestioned. The political and economic thought of the late eighteenth century--the old, lost idyll of universal freedom--is itself, now, newly familiar. Condorcet wrote of the new society of the United States, in 1786, that "the spectacle of a great people where the rights of man are respected is useful to all others ... It teaches us that these rights are everywhere the same." Of the French Revolution, he wrote in 1791 that it had "opened up an immense scope to the hopes of the human species ... [T]his revolution is not in a government, it is in opinions and wills."

    The new prospects of the early twenty-first century have something of this vastness, this sense of an unbounded future. We may also have more sympathy, in our societies of universal commerce, for the endless uncertainty, the unquiet imagination, which were believed, in the late eighteenth century, to be the consequences of commercial freedom. The effort to look at eighteenth-century economic thought in its own context might also, in these circumstances, cast light on our context, and our economic politics.

Excerpted from ECONOMIC SENTIMENTS by EMMA ROTHSCHILD. Copyright © 2001 by President and Fellows of Harvard College. Excerpted by permission. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.

Rewards Program