did-you-know? rent-now

Amazon no longer offers textbook rentals. We do!

did-you-know? rent-now

Amazon no longer offers textbook rentals. We do!

We're the #1 textbook rental company. Let us show you why.

9780521685573

The Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of Early Ideas about Probability, Induction and Statistical Inference

by
  • ISBN13:

    9780521685573

  • ISBN10:

    0521685575

  • Edition: 2nd
  • Format: Paperback
  • Copyright: 2006-07-31
  • Publisher: Cambridge University Press
  • Purchase Benefits
List Price: $31.99 Save up to $0.96
  • Buy New
    $31.03

    USUALLY SHIPS IN 2-3 BUSINESS DAYS

Supplemental Materials

What is included with this book?

Summary

Historical records show that there was no real concept of probability in Europe before the mid-seventeenth century, although the use of dice and other randomizing objects was commonplace. Ian Hacking presents a philosophical critique of early ideas about probability, induction, and statistical inference and the growth of this new family of ideas in the fifteenth, sixteenth, and seventeenth centuries. Hacking invokes a wide intellectual framework involving the growth of science, economics, and the theology of the period. He argues that the transformations that made it possible for probability concepts to emerge have constrained all subsequent development of probability theory and determine the space within which philosophical debate on the subject is still conducted. First published in 1975, this edition includes a new introduction that contextualizes his book in light of new work and philosophical trends. Ian Hacking is the winner of the Holberg International Memorial Prize 2009.

Author Biography

Ian Hacking holds the chair of philosophy and history of scientific concepts at the College de France

Table of Contents

1 An absent family of ideas
1(10)
Although dicing is one of the oldest of human pastimes, there is no known mathematics of randomness until the Renaissance.
None of the explanations of this fact is compelling.
2 Duality
11(7)
Probability, as we now conceive it, came into being about 1660.
It was essentially dual, on the one hand having to do with degrees of belief, on the other, with devices tending to produce stable long-run frequencies.
3 Opinion
18(13)
In the Renaissance, what was then called 'probability' was an attribute of opinion, in contrast to knowledge, which could only be obtained by demonstration.
A probable opinion was not one supported by evidence, but one which was approved by some authority, or by the testimony of respected judges.
4 Evidence
31(8)
Until the end of the Renaissance, one of our concepts of evidence was lacking: that by which one thing can indicate, contingently, the state of something else.
Demonstration, versimilitude and testimony were all familiar concepts, but not this further idea of the inductive evidence of things,
5 Signs
39(10)
Probability is a child of the low sciences, such as alchemy or medicine, which had to deal in opinion, whereas the high sciences, such as astronomy or mechanics, aimed at demonstrable knowledge.
A chief concept of the low sciences was that of the sign, here described in some detail.
Observation of signs was conceived of as reading testimony.
Signs were more or less reliable.
Thus on the one hand a sign made an opinion probable (in the old sense of Chapter 3) because it was furnished by the best testimony of all.
On the other hand, signs could be assessed by the frequency with which they spoke truly.
At the end of the Renaissance, the sign was transformed into the concept of evidence described in Chapter 4.
This new kind of evidence conferred probability on propositions, namely made them worthy of approval.
But it did so in virtue of the frequency with which it made correct predictions.
This transformation from sign into evidence is the key to the emergence of a concept of probability that is dual in the sense of Chapter 2.
6 The first calculations
49(8)
Some isolated calculations on chances, made before 1660, are briefly described.
7 The Roannez circle (1654)
57(6)
Some problems solved by Pascal set probability rolling.
From here until Chapter 17 Leibniz is used as a witness to the early days of probability theory.
8 The great decision (1658?)
63(10)
'Pascal's wager' for acting as if one believed in God is the first well-understood contribution to decision theory.
9 The art of thinking (1662)
73(12)
Something actually called 'probability' is first measured in the Port Royal Logic, which is also one of the first works to distinguish evidence, in the sense of Chapter 4, from testimony.
The new awareness of probability, evidence and conventional (as opposed to natural) sign, is illustrated by work of Wilkins, first in 1640, before the emergence of probability, and then in 1668 after the emergence.
10 Probability and the law (1665) 85(7)
While young and ignorant of the Paris developments Leibniz proposed to measure degrees of proof and right in taw on a scale between 0 and 1 subject to a crude calculation of what he called 'probability'.
11 Expectation (1657) 92(10)
Huygens wrote the first printed textbook of probability using expectation as the central concept.
His justification of this concept is still of interest.
12 Political arithmetic (1662) 102(9)
Graunt drew the first detailed statistical inferences from the hills of mortality for the city of London, and Petty urged the need for a central statistical office.
13 Annuities (1671) 111(11)
Hudde and de Witt used Dutch annuity records to infer a mortality curve On which to work out the fair price for an annuity.
14 Equipossibility (1678) 122(12)
The definition of probability as a ratio among 'equally possible cases' originates with Leibniz.
The definition, unintelligible to us, was natural at the time, for possibility was either de re (about things) or de dicto (about propositions).
Probability was likewise either about things, in the frequency sense, or about propositions, in the epistemic sense.
Thus the duality of probability was preserved by the duality of possibility.
15 Inductive logic 134(9)
Leibniz anticipated Carnap's notion of inductive logic.
He could do so because of the central place occupied by the concept of possibility in his scheme of metaphysics.
Within that scheme, a global system of inductive logic makes more sense than Carnap's does in our modern metaphysics.
16 The art of conjecturing (1692[?] published 1713) 143(11)
The emergence of probability is completed with Jacques Bernoulli's book, which both undertakes a self-conscious analysis of the concept of probability, and proves the first limit theorem.
17 The first limit theorem 154(12)
The possible interpretations of Bernoulli's theorem are described.
18 Design 166(10)
The English conception of probability in the early eighteenth century, guided by the Newtonian philosophy espoused by members of the Royal Society, interprets the stability of stochastic processes proven by the limit theorems as evidence of divine design.
19 Induction (1737) 176(10)
Hume's sceptical problem of induction could not have arisen much before 1660, for there was no concept of inductive evidence in terms of which to raise it.
Why did it have to wait until 1737?
So long as it was still believed that demonstrative knowledge was possible, a knowledge in which causes were proved from first principles, then Hume's argument could always be stopped.
It was necessary that the distinction between opinion and knowledge should become a matter of degree.
That means that high and low science had to collapse into one another.
This had been an ongoing process throughout the seventeenth century.
It was formalized by Berkeley who said that all causes were merely signs.
Causes had been the prerogative of high science, and signs the tool of the low.
Berkeley identified them and Hume thereby became possible.
Bibliography 186(17)
Index 203

Supplemental Materials

What is included with this book?

The New copy of this book will include any supplemental materials advertised. Please check the title of the book to determine if it should include any access cards, study guides, lab manuals, CDs, etc.

The Used, Rental and eBook copies of this book are not guaranteed to include any supplemental materials. Typically, only the book itself is included. This is true even if the title states it includes any access cards, study guides, lab manuals, CDs, etc.

Rewards Program