rent-now

Rent More, Save More! Use code: ECRENTAL

5% off 1 book, 7% off 2 books, 10% off 3+ books

9780810106055

The Foundations of Arithmetic

by ;
  • ISBN13:

    9780810106055

  • ISBN10:

    0810106051

  • Edition: 2nd
  • Format: Paperback
  • Copyright: 1980-06-01
  • Publisher: Northwestern Univ Pr

Note: Supplemental materials are not guaranteed with Rental or Used book purchases.

Purchase Benefits

  • Free Shipping Icon Free Shipping On Orders Over $35!
    Your order must be $35 or more to qualify for free economy shipping. Bulk sales, PO's, Marketplace items, eBooks and apparel do not qualify for this offer.
  • eCampus.com Logo Get Rewarded for Ordering Your Textbooks! Enroll Now
List Price: $25.60 Save up to $18.69
  • Rent Book
    $6.91
    Add to Cart Free Shipping Icon Free Shipping

    TERM
    PRICE
    DUE
    IN STOCK USUALLY SHIPS IN 24 HOURS.
    HURRY! ONLY 1 COPY IN STOCK AT THIS PRICE
    *This item is part of an exclusive publisher rental program and requires an additional convenience fee. This fee will be reflected in the shopping cart.

How To: Textbook Rental

Looking to rent a book? Rent The Foundations of Arithmetic [ISBN: 9780810106055] for the semester, quarter, and short term or search our site for other textbooks by Frege, Gottlob; Austin, J. L.. Renting a textbook can save you up to 90% from the cost of buying.

Table of Contents

Recent work in mathematics has shown a tendency towards rigour of proof and sharp definition of concepts
1(1)
This critical examination must ultimately extend to the concept of Number itself. The aim of proof
2(1)
Philosophical motives for such an enquiry: the controversies as to whether the laws of number are analytic or synthetic, a priori or a posteriori. Sense of these expressions
3(1)
Task of the present work
4(1)
I. Views of certain writers on the nature of arithmetical propositions
Are numerical formulae provable?
Kant denies this, which Hankel justly calls a paradox
5(2)
Leibniz's proof that 2 + 2 = 4 contains a gap. Grassman's definition of a + b is faulty
7(2)
Mill's view that the definitions of the individual numbers assert observed facts, from which the calculations follow, is without foundation
9(2)
These definitions do not require, for their legitimacy, the observation of his facts
11(1)
Are the laws of arithmetic inductive truths?
Mill's law of nature. In calling arithmetical truths laws of nature, Mill is confusing them with their applications
12(2)
Grounds for denying that the laws of addition are inductive truths: numbers not all of the same sort; the definition of number does not of itself yield any set of common properties of numbers; probably the reverse is true and induction should be based on arithmetic
14(3)
Leibniz's term ``innate''
17(1)
Are the laws of arithmetic synthetic a priori or analytic?
Kant. Baumann. Lipschitz. Hankel. Inner intuition as the ground of knowledge
17(2)
Distinction between arithmetic and geometry
19(1)
Comparison between the various kinds of truths in respect of the domains that they govern
20(1)
Views of Leibniz and W. S. Jevons
21(1)
Against them, Mill's ridicule of the ``artful manipulation of language''. Symbols are not empty simply because not meaning anything with which we can be acquainted
22(1)
Inadequacy of induction. Conjecture that the laws of number are analytic judgments; what in that case is the use of them. Estimate of the value of analytic judgments
23(1)
II. Views of certain writers on the concept of Number
Necessity for an enquiry into the general concept of Number
24(1)
Its definition not to be geometrical
25(1)
Is number definable? Hankel. Leibniz
26(1)
Is Number a property of external things?
Views of M. Cantor and E. Schroder
27(1)
Opposite view of Baumann: external things present us with no strict units. Their number apparently dependent on our way of regarding them
28(1)
Mill's view untenable, that the number is a property of the agglomeration of things
29(1)
Wide range of applicability of number. Mill. Locke. Leibniz's immaterial metaphysical figure. If number were something sensible, it could not be ascribed to anything non-sensible
30(2)
Mill's physical difference between 2 and 3. Number according to Berkeley not really existent in things but created by the mind
32(1)
Is number something subjective?
Lipschitz's description of the construction of numbers will not do, and cannot take the place of a definition of the concept. Number not an object for psychology, but something objective
33(3)
Number is not, as Schloemilch claims, the idea of the position of an item in a series
36(2)
Numbers as sets
Thomae's name-giving
38(1)
III. Views on unity and one
Does the number word ``one'' express a property of objects?
Ambiguity of the terms ``μoναs'' and ``unit''. E. Schroder's definition of the unit as an object to be numbered is apparently pointless. The adjective ``one'' does not add anything to a description, cannot serve as a predicate
39(2)
Attempts to define unity by Leibniz and Baumann seem to blur the concept completely
41(1)
Baumann's criteria, being undivided and being isolated. The notion of unity not suggested to us by every object (as Locke)
41(1)
Still, language does indicate some connexion with being undivided and isolated, with a shift of meaning however
42(1)
Indivisibility (G. Kopp) as a criterion of the unit is untenable
43(1)
Are units identical with one another?
Identity as the reason for the name ``unit''. E. Schroder. Hobbes. Hume. Thomae. To abstract from the differences between things does not give us the concept of their Number, nor does it make the things identical with one another
44(2)
Indeed diversity is actually necessary, if we are to speak of plurality. Descartes. E. Schroder. W. S. Jevons
46(1)
The view that units are different also comes up against difficulties. Different distinct ones in W. S. Jevons
46(2)
Definitions of number in terms of the unit or one by Locke, Leibniz and Hesse
48(1)
``One'' is a proper name, ``unit'' a concept word. Number cannot be defined as units. Distinction between ``and'' and +
48(2)
The difficulty of reconciling identity of units with distinguishability is concealed by the ambiguity of ``unit''
50(1)
Attempts to overcome the difficulty
Space and time as means of distinguishing between units. Hobbes. Thomae. Against them: Leibniz, Baumann, W. S. Jevons
51(2)
The purpose not achieved
53(1)
Position in a series as a means of distinguishing between units. Hankel's putting
54(1)
Schroder's copying of objects by the symbol I
54(1)
Jevons' abstraction from the character of the differences while retaining the fact of their existence. 0 and 1 are numbers like the rest. The difficulty still remains
55(3)
Solution of the difficulty
Recapitulation
58(1)
A statement of number contains an assertion about a concept. Objection that the number varies while the concept does not
59(1)
That statements of number are statements of fact explained by the objectivity of concepts
60(1)
Removal of certain difficulties
61(1)
Corroboration found in Spinoza
62(1)
E. Schroder's account quoted
62(1)
Correction of the same
63(1)
Corroboration found in a German idiom
64(1)
Distinction between component characteristics of a concept and its properties. Existence and number
64(1)
Unit the name given to the subject of a statement of number. How indivisible and isolated. How identical and distinguishable
65(2)
IV. The concept of Number
Every individual number is a self-subsistent object
Attempt to complete the definitions of the individual numbers as given by Leibniz
67(1)
The attempted definitions are unusable, because what they define is a predicate in which the number is only an element
67(1)
A statement of number should be regarded as an identity between numbers
68(1)
Objection that we can form no idea of number as a self-subsistent object. In principle number cannot be imagined
69(1)
Because we cannot imagine an object, we are not to be debarred from investigating it
70(1)
Even concrete things are not always imaginable. In seeking the meaning of a word, we must consider it in the context of a proposition
71(1)
Objection that numbers are not spatial. Not every objective object is spatial
72(1)
To obtain the concept of Number, we must fix the sense of a numerical identity
We need a criterion for numerical identity
73(1)
Possible criterion in one-one correlation. Doubt as to the logic of defining identity specially for the case of numbers
73(1)
Examples of similar procedures: direction of a line, orientation of a plane, shape of a triangle
74(2)
Attempt at a definition. A second doubt: are the laws of identity satisfied?
76(1)
Third doubt: the criterion of identity fails to cover all cases
77(1)
We cannot supplement it by taking as a defining characteristic of a concept the way in which an object is introduced
78(1)
Number as the extension of a concept
79(1)
Elucidation
80(1)
Our definition completed and its worth proved
The relation-concept
81(2)
Correlation by means of a relation
83(1)
One-one relations. The concept of Number
84(1)
The Number which belongs to the concept F is identical with the Number which belongs to the concept G, if there exists a relation which correlates one to one the objects falling under F with those falling under G
85(1)
Nought is the Number which belongs to the concept ``not identical with itself''
86(2)
Nought is the Number which belongs to a concept under which nothing falls. No object falls under a concept if nought is the Number belonging to that concept
88(1)
Definition of the expression ``n follows in the series of natural numbers directly after m''
89(1)
I is the Number which belongs to the concept ``identical with o''
90(1)
Propositions to be proved by means of our definitions
91(1)
Definition of following in a series
92(1)
Comments on the same. Following is objective
92(2)
Definition of the expression ``x is a member of the &phis;-series ending with y''
94(1)
Outline of the proof that there is no last member of the series of natural numbers
94(1)
Definition of finite Number. No finite Number follows in the series of natural numbers after itself
95(1)
Infinite Numbers
The Number which belongs to the concept ``finite Number'' is an infinite Number
96(1)
Cantor's infinite Numbers; ``power.'' Divergence in terminology
97(1)
Cantor's following in the succession and my following in the series
98(1)
V. Conclusion
Nature of the laws of arithmetic
99(1)
Kant's underestimate of the value of analytic judgments
99(2)
Kant's dictum: ``Without sensibility no object would be given to us.'' Kant's services to mathematics
101(1)
For the complete proof of the analytic nature of the laws of arithmetic we still need a chain of deductions with no link missing
102(1)
My concept writing makes it possible to supply this lack
103(1)
Other numbers
The sense, according to Hankel, of asking whether some number is possible
104(1)
Numbers are neither outside us in space nor subjective
105(1)
That a concept is free from contradiction is no guarantee that anything falls under it, and itself requires to be proved
105(1)
We cannot regard (c-b) without more ado as a symbol which solves the problem of subtraction
106(1)
Not even the mathematician can create things at will
107(1)
Concepts are to be distinguished from objects
108(1)
Hankel's definition of addition
108(1)
The formalist theory defective
109(1)
Attempt to produce an interpretation of complex numbers by extending the meaning of multiplication in some special way
110(1)
The cogency of proofs is affected, unless it is possible to produce such an interpretation
111(1)
The mere postulate that it shall be possible to carry out some operation is not the same as its own fulfilment
111(1)
Kossack's definition of complex numbers is only a guide towards a definition, and fails to avoid the importation of foreign elements. Geometrical representation of complex numbers
112(2)
What is needed is to fix the sense of a recognition-judgment for the case of the new numbers
114(1)
The charm of arithmetic lies in its rationality
115(1)
Recapitulation
115

Supplemental Materials

What is included with this book?

The New copy of this book will include any supplemental materials advertised. Please check the title of the book to determine if it should include any access cards, study guides, lab manuals, CDs, etc.

The Used, Rental and eBook copies of this book are not guaranteed to include any supplemental materials. Typically, only the book itself is included. This is true even if the title states it includes any access cards, study guides, lab manuals, CDs, etc.

Rewards Program